Realisms and Anti-Realisms: Do Our Minds Tell the Truth About Themselves?

At the heart of philosophy—especially the philosophy of mind—lies a deceptively simple question: Are the things we talk about real? When we say someone “believes” something, or that they “want” something, are we pointing to actual entities or processes in the mind? Or are we using a convenient fiction, a helpful story that works, but doesn’t quite map onto what’s really going on?


This brings us into the profound and ongoing debate between realism and anti-realism. While these terms span many domains—from ethics to science to mathematics—nowhere is their tension more revealing than in our understanding of the human mind.





What Is Realism?



In its simplest form, realism is the belief that there is a mind-independent reality that our concepts and theories try to describe. A realist about psychology believes that when we talk about mental states like belief, desire, fear, or joy, we are referring to actual, objective features of human minds—features that exist regardless of whether we understand them perfectly, or even at all.


So, under realism:


  • Beliefs are real things—possibly brain states or information structures.
  • Desires are genuine causal forces that influence behavior.
  • Our folk-psychological terms may be rough, but they point to something fundamentally true.



This view gives weight to introspection, accountability, and mental health. If mental states are real, they can be studied, mapped, and treated. They can be causes in scientific explanations, not just labels for what we don’t understand.





What Is Anti-Realism?



Anti-realism, by contrast, is skeptical about this assumption. Anti-realists don’t necessarily deny that people feel or think—but they question whether our common ways of talking about those experiences actually track real things. Instead, they suggest that mental concepts might be:


  • Useful fictions that help us predict behavior without revealing internal reality.
  • Cultural artifacts, shaped by history, language, and social norms.
  • Tools for communication, not descriptions of what’s “out there.”



An anti-realist might say: “Belief” is not a thing in the brain. It’s a construct we use to describe complex behavior in a way that makes sense to us. Just as early scientists used “phlogiston” to explain fire (a concept later discarded), we may one day discard “belief” and “desire” in favor of more precise, neuroscientific accounts.





Realism vs. Anti-Realism in Psychology



Nowhere is this debate more urgent than in psychology and cognitive science.


Realists argue that folk psychology—the way we naturally talk about thoughts and feelings—is a rough but reliable guide to mental reality. They believe it can be refined and eventually integrated with scientific psychology, providing a full picture of how minds work.


Anti-realists, however, point out that mental terms are often vague, culturally variable, and riddled with exceptions. They ask: if no two people have the same definition of “love” or “intention,” how can these be real categories? Some go even further and advocate for eliminativism—the idea that future science will discard these concepts entirely, just as astronomy abandoned the idea of crystal spheres.





Why This Debate Matters



This may sound like abstract theorizing, but it touches every part of our lives:


  • Mental health: If depression is real, we can treat it biologically. If it’s just a cultural narrative, treatment might be more about reshaping stories than brain chemistry.
  • Legal responsibility: Are people truly responsible for their actions if “intention” is just a useful fiction?
  • AI and machines: Can machines really “know” or “think” if those terms don’t point to real internal states?
  • Self-understanding: When you say “I believe in myself,” are you describing a real condition—or just telling yourself something useful?






A Middle Path: Pragmatic Realism?



Some thinkers propose a third view: pragmatic realism. According to this approach, we can treat concepts like belief, desire, and consciousness as real enough—as long as they do useful work. We don’t need perfect definitions or absolute certainty to act as if mental states are real. Instead, we can acknowledge their fuzziness while still valuing their explanatory power.


This mirrors how we treat other complex systems. Economists talk about “markets” and “confidence” even though these are not tangible things. Meteorologists speak of “fronts” and “pressure systems,” which are patterns, not particles. In the same way, beliefs and desires might be real as patterns of information, behavior, and cause—not as simple, reducible objects.





Final Thoughts: Facing the Mind Honestly



Realism and anti-realism are more than academic postures. They are orientations toward reality itself. Realism seeks truth—however complex, messy, or mysterious. Anti-realism seeks humility—recognizing the limits of language, perception, and theory.


In a way, both are necessary. We need realism to pursue knowledge, meaning, and ethical accountability. And we need anti-realism to remind us that the mind might not fit neatly into our favorite theories.


In the end, perhaps the most honest position is this: the mind is real, but not necessarily as we imagine it. It resists simple labels. It reveals itself in layers. And it forces us to confront one of the oldest questions we can ask:


What does it mean to know ourselves—and to be known?